The Toque Game (for winter
months).
Alice and her two friends Bob and Chris are selected to play the "Toque game": They will be seated so that each can see the others. Each will be given a bag containing two toques, one with a white pompom and one with a red pompom. They will then be blindfolded and each will pick a toque at random out of the bag and put it on. When the blindfolds are removed, the players will be able to see the pompom on the other's toque, but not their own. They will not be allowed to communicate by gestures or shouting, and they will have to whisper to a referee standing next to them either "I guess my pompom is white", "I guess my pompom is red", or "I pass". If at least one of them guesses right and nobody guesses wrong, they all win a trip to Moose Jaw, Saskatchewan. Otherwise they just get popcorn. Alice and her friends can devise a strategy before the game to give them better odds. For instance, they could decide that Alice alone will guess and the others will pass; such a strategy gives them a fifty percent chance of winning. Is there a way to do better?
Solution to
MP46
Our statement of the problem should have emphasized that the rules
of the game permit no signals of any kind. The three players guess
simultaneously, and their words are heard only by the referees, not by the other
participants. More to the point, the solution must make use of mathematical
reasoning, with no trickery. Several of our respondents suggested winning
strategies that involved signals much like those used in the game of bridge.
Nevertheless we received optimal strategies from Alex Akulov (Regina), Xavier
Hecquet (France), Wolfgang Kais (Germany), Patrick LoPresti (USA), Dat Phan
(Regina), and Lionel Ruiz (France).
The optimal strategy:
If you see two pompoms of the same colour, guess that your pompom has the opposite colour. Otherwise, pass.
Using this strategy the team will have a 75% chance of winning. To
see why, note that there are eight possible arrangements of colours; each of
them are equally likely:
Alice
|
Bob
|
Chris
|
---|---|---|
Red
|
Red
|
Red
|
Red
|
Red
|
White
|
Red
|
White
|
Red
|
Red
|
White
|
White
|
White
|
Red
|
Red
|
White
|
Red
|
White
|
White
|
White
|
Red
|
White
|
White
|
White
|
In two of these cases, the first and last, the pompoms all have
the same colour. By using our strategy here, each participant will guess
incorrectly (choosing the opposite colour), so that the team will lose two times
out of eight. In the remaining six cases, one pompom has a colour different from
the other two. So in the second case, for example, Alice and Bob have red, while
Chris has white. Both Alice and Bob will see both colours and pass, while Chris
sees two reds and he guesses white. With this strategy the team will win in all
six of the mixed cases, so their probability of success will be 75%.
Note that any individual still has only a 50-50 chance of guessing
correctly, but it is the team that wins or loses, not the individual. What makes
the strategy work is that all of the wrong guesses are gathered together into
the two losing cases. There is a lesson to be learned here – In the words of
Gadiel Seroussi, director of information theory research at HP Labs, “If the
evidence suggests that someone on your team knows more than you, you should keep
your mouth shut.”
But, is it possible to do better than 75%? The answer is
no, when playing by the rules and using a deterministic strategy. Here
is Patrick Lo Presti’s argument. Consider any case C which the team wins. At
least one player X guesses correctly. Let C' be the case in which X has his
colour switched, but his teammates keep their colours. Then X sees what he saw
in case C, but in case C' he guesses incorrectly, and the team loses. By
carefully arguing that switching all three colours from case C' to its
complementary case will similarly lead to a loss, we see that there must be at
least two losing cases.
Further comments.
Of course the same game can be played with any number of players.
The general problem is to find a strategy for a team of n players that
maximizes its chances of winning. In this form the game reduces to a problem in
coding theory and, as such, has applications to error correcting codes (the
codes that make data transmission, cell phones, and CDs possible), and to
covering codes (which are used to compress data so it takes up less space in a
computer’s memory). There seems to be serious mathematics related to the game,
but the optimal strategy is not known for n in general. There is a nice
discussion of the problem in the New York Times (April 10, 2001; see
http://www.worlds-fastest-website.com/why-mathematicians-care-about-hat-color.htm).
We have also seen articles about it in Scientific
American, and in Focus, the newsletter of the Mathematical
Association of America. (Sorry, we cannot be more precise with our references at
this time.)
math
central
댓글 없음:
댓글 쓰기