In mathematics, an irrational number is any real number that cannot be
expressed as a ratio a/b, where a and b are integers and b is
non-zero.
Informally, this means
that an irrational number cannot be represented as a simple fraction. Irrational
numbers are those real numbers that cannot be represented as terminating or repeating decimals. As a
consequence of Cantor's proof that the real
numbers are uncountable (and the rationals countable) it
follows that almost all real numbers are irrational.[1]
When the ratio of lengths of two line segments is
irrational, the line segments are also described as being incommensurable, meaning
they share no measure in common.
Perhaps the best-known
irrational numbers are: the ratio of a circle's circumference to its diameter π, Euler's number e, the golden ratio φ, and the square root of two √2.[2][3][4]
The famous mathematical constant pi (π) is among the most well-known
irrational numbers and is much-represented in popular culture
History[edit]
It has been suggested
that the concept of irrationality was implicitly accepted by Indian mathematicians since the 7th century BC,
when Manava (c. 750 – 690 BC)
believed that the square roots of numbers such as 2 and 61 could not
be exactly determined.[5] However,
historian Carl Benjamin Boyer[6] states that
"...such claims are not well substantiated and unlikely to be true."
Ancient Greece[edit]
The first proof of the
existence of irrational numbers is usually attributed to a Pythagorean (possibly Hippasus of Metapontum),[7] who probably
discovered them while identifying sides of the pentagram.[8] The
then-current Pythagorean method would have claimed that there must be some
sufficiently small, indivisible unit that could fit evenly into one of these
lengths as well as the other. However, Hippasus, in the 5th century BC, was able
to deduce that there was in fact no common unit of measure, and that the
assertion of such an existence was in fact a contradiction. He did this by
demonstrating that if the hypotenuse of an isosceles right triangle was
indeed commensurable with a leg,
then that unit of measure must be both odd and even, which is impossible. His
reasoning is as follows:
-
- Start with an isosceles right triangle with side lengths of integers a, b, and c. The ratio of the hypotenuse to a leg is represented by c:b.
- Assume a, b, and c are in the smallest possible terms (i.e. they have no common factors).
- By the Pythagorean theorem: c2 = a2+b2 = b2+b2 = 2b2. (Since the triangle is isosceles, a = b).
- Since c2 = 2b2, c2 is divisible by 2, and therefore even.
- Since c2 is even, c must be even.
- Since c and b have no common factors, and c is even, b must be odd (if b were even, b and c would have a common factor of 2).
- Since c is even, dividing c by 2 yields an integer. Let y be this integer (c = 2y).
- Squaring both sides of c = 2y yields c2 = (2y)2, or c2 = 4y2.
- Substituting 4y2 for c2 in the first equation (c2 = 2b2) gives us 4y2= 2b2.
- Dividing by 2 yields 2y2 = b2.
- Since y is an integer, and 2y2 = b2, b2 is divisible by 2, and therefore even.
- Since b2 is even, b must be even.
- However, we have already asserted that b must be odd, and b cannot be both odd and even. This contradiction proves that c and b cannot both be integers, and thus the existence of a number that cannot be expressed as a ratio of two integers.[9]
Greek mathematicians termed
this ratio of incommensurable magnitudes alogos, or inexpressible.
Hippasus, however, was not lauded for his efforts: according to one legend, he
made his discovery while out at sea, and was subsequently thrown overboard by
his fellow Pythagoreans “…for having produced an element in the universe which
denied the…doctrine that all phenomena in the universe can be reduced to whole
numbers and their ratios.”[10] Another legend
states that Hippasus was merely exiled for this revelation. Whatever the
consequence to Hippasus himself, his discovery posed a very serious problem to
Pythagorean mathematics, since it shattered the assumption that number and
geometry were inseparable–a foundation of their theory.
The discovery of
incommensurable ratios was indicative of another problem facing the Greeks: the
relation of the discrete to the continuous. Brought into light by Zeno of Elea, who questioned
the conception that quantities are discrete and composed of a finite number of
units of a given size. Past Greek conceptions dictated that they necessarily
must be, for “whole numbers represent discrete objects, and a commensurable
ratio represents a relation between two collections of discrete objects.”[11] However Zeno
found that in fact “[quantities] in general are not discrete collections of
units; this is why ratios of incommensurable [quantities] appear….[Q]uantities
are, in other words, continuous.”[11] What this
means is that, contrary to the popular conception of the time, there cannot be
an indivisible, smallest unit of measure for any quantity. That in fact, these
divisions of quantity must necessarily be infinite. For example, consider a line segment:
this segment can be split in half, that half split in half, the half of the half
in half, and so on. This process can continue infinitely, for there is always
another half to be split. The more times the segment is halved, the closer the
unit of measure comes to zero, but it never reaches exactly zero. This is just
what Zeno sought to prove. He sought to prove this by formulating four paradoxes, which
demonstrated the contradictions inherent in the mathematical thought of the
time. While Zeno’s paradoxes accurately demonstrated the deficiencies of current
mathematical conceptions, they were not regarded as proof of the alternative. In
the minds of the Greeks, disproving the validity of one view did not necessarily
prove the validity of another, and therefore further investigation had to
occur.
The next step was taken
by Eudoxus of Cnidus, who formalized a new theory of
proportion that took into account commensurable as well as incommensurable
quantities. Central to his idea was the distinction between magnitude and
number. A magnitude “...was not a number but stood for entities such as line
segments, angles, areas, volumes, and time which could vary, as we would say,
continuously. Magnitudes were opposed to numbers, which jumped from one value to
another, as from 4 to 5.”[12] Numbers are
composed of some smallest, indivisible unit, whereas magnitudes are infinitely
reducible. Because no quantitative values were assigned to magnitudes, Eudoxus
was then able to account for both commensurable and incommensurable ratios by
defining a ratio in terms of its magnitude, and proportion as an equality
between two ratios. By taking quantitative values (numbers) out of the equation,
he avoided the trap of having to express an irrational number as a number.
“Eudoxus’ theory enabled the Greek mathematicians to make tremendous progress in
geometry by supplying the necessary logical foundation for incommensurable
ratios.”[13] Book 10 is
dedicated to classification of irrational magnitudes.
As a result of the
distinction between number and magnitude, geometry became the only method that
could take into account incommensurable ratios. Because previous numerical
foundations were still incompatible with the concept of incommensurability,
Greek focus shifted away from those numerical conceptions such as algebra and
focused almost exclusively on geometry. In fact, in many cases algebraic
conceptions were reformulated into geometrical terms. This may account for why
we still conceive of x2 or x3 as x squared and x cubed
instead of x second power and x third power. Also crucial to Zeno’s work with
incommensurable magnitudes was the fundamental focus on deductive reasoning that
resulted from the foundational shattering of earlier Greek mathematics. The
realization that some basic conception within the existing theory was at odds
with reality necessitated a complete and thorough investigation of the axioms
and assumptions that comprised that theory. Out of this necessity Eudoxus
developed his method of exhaustion, a kind of reductio ad absurdum that “…established the
deductive organization on the basis of explicit axioms…” as well as “…reinforced
the earlier decision to rely on deductive reasoning for proof.”[14] This method of
exhaustion is the first step in the creation of calculus.
Theodorus of Cyrene proved the irrationality of the
surds of whole numbers up to
17, but stopped there probably because the algebra he used couldn't be applied
to the square root of 17.[15] It wasn't
until Eudoxus developed a theory of proportion that took
into account irrational as well as rational ratios that a strong mathematical
foundation of irrational numbers was created.[16]
Geometrical and mathematical problems involving irrational numbers such as square roots were addressed very early during the Vedic period in India and there are references to such calculations in the Samhitas, Brahmanas and more notably in the Sulbha sutras (800 BC or earlier). (See Bag, Indian Journal of History of Science, 25(1-4), 1990).
It is suggested that Aryabhata (5th century AD) in calculating a value of pi to 5 significant figures, he used the word āsanna (approaching), to mean that not only is this an approximation but that the value is incommensurable (or irrational).
Later, in their treatises, Indian mathematicians wrote on the arithmetic of surds including addition, subtraction, multiplication, rationalization, as well as separation and extraction of square roots. (See Datta, Singh, Indian Journal of History of Science, 28(3), 1993).
Mathematicians like Brahmagupta (in 628 AD) and Bhaskara I (in 629 AD) made contributions in this area as did other mathematicians who followed. In the 12th century Bhaskara II evaluated some of these formulas and critiqued them, identifying their limitations.
During the 14th to 16th
centuries, Madhava of Sangamagrama and
the Kerala school of astronomy and
mathematics discovered the infinite series for several
irrational numbers such as π and certain irrational values of trigonometric functions. Jyesthadeva provided proofs for these infinite
series in the Yuktibhāṣā.[17]
Middle Ages[edit]
In the Middle ages, the development of algebra by Muslim mathematicians
allowed irrational numbers to be treated as algebraic objects.[18] Middle Eastern
mathematicians also merged the concepts of "number" and "magnitude" into a more
general idea of real numbers, criticized Euclid's idea of ratios, developed the theory of composite ratios,
and extended the concept of number to ratios of continuous magnitude.[19] In his
commentary on Book 10 of the Elements, the Persian mathematician Al-Mahani (d. 874/884) examined and classified quadratic irrationals and cubic irrationals. He
provided definitions for rational and irrational magnitudes, which he treated as
irrational numbers. He dealt with them freely but explains them in geometric
terms as follows:[20]
"It will be a rational (magnitude) when we, for instance, say 10, 12, 3%, 6%, etc., because its value is pronounced and expressed quantitatively. What is not rational is irrational and it is impossible to pronounce and represent its value quantitatively. For example: the roots of numbers such as 10, 15, 20 which are not squares, the sides of numbers which are not cubes etc."
In contrast to Euclid's
concept of magnitudes as lines, Al-Mahani considered integers and fractions as
rational magnitudes, and square roots and cube roots as irrational magnitudes. He also
introduced an arithmetical approach to the
concept of irrationality, as he attributes the following to irrational
magnitudes:[20]
"their sums or differences, or results of their addition to a rational magnitude, or results of subtracting a magnitude of this kind from an irrational one, or of a rational magnitude from it."
The Egyptian mathematician Abū Kāmil Shujā ibn Aslam
(c. 850 – 930) was the first to accept irrational numbers as solutions to quadratic equations or as coefficients in an equation, often in the form of square roots, cube
roots and fourth roots.[21] In the 10th
century, the Iraqi mathematician
Al-Hashimi provided general proofs (rather than geometric demonstrations) for
irrational numbers, as he considered multiplication, division, and other
arithmetical functions.[22] Abū Ja'far al-Khāzin
(900–971) provides a definition of rational and irrational magnitudes, stating
that if a definite quantity is:[23]
"contained in a certain given magnitude once or many times, then this (given) magnitude corresponds to a rational number. . . . Each time when this (latter) magnitude comprises a half, or a third, or a quarter of the given magnitude (of the unit), or, compared with (the unit), comprises three, five, or three fifths, it is a rational magnitude. And, in general, each magnitude that corresponds to this magnitude (i.e. to the unit), as one number to another, is rational. If, however, a magnitude cannot be represented as a multiple, a part (l/n), or parts (m/n) of a given magnitude, it is irrational, i.e. it cannot be expressed other than by means of roots."
Many of these concepts
were eventually accepted by European mathematicians sometime after the Latin translations of the 12th
century. Al-Hassār, a Moroccan mathematician from Fez specializing in Islamic inheritance
jurisprudence during the 12th century, first mentions the use of
a fractional bar, where numerators and denominators are separated by a
horizontal bar. In his discussion he writes, "..., for example, if you are told
to write three-fifths and a third of a fifth, write thus,
."
[24] This same
fractional notation appears soon after in the work of Leonardo Fibonacci in the 13th century.[25]
Modern period[edit]
The 17th century saw imaginary numbers become a
powerful tool in the hands of Abraham de Moivre, and especially of Leonhard Euler. The
completion of the theory of complex numbers in the 19th century entailed the
differentiation of irrationals into algebraic and transcendental numbers, the
proof of the existence of transcendental numbers, and the resurgence of the
scientific study of the theory of irrationals, largely ignored since Euclid. The year 1872 saw the publication of the
theories of Karl Weierstrass (by his pupil Ernst Kossak), Eduard Heine (Crelle's Journal, 74), Georg Cantor (Annalen, 5), and Richard Dedekind. Méray had
taken in 1869 the same point of departure as Heine, but the theory is generally
referred to the year 1872. Weierstrass's method has been completely set forth by
Salvatore Pincherle in 1880,[26] and Dedekind's
has received additional prominence through the author's later work (1888) and
the endorsement by Paul Tannery (1894). Weierstrass, Cantor, and Heine
base their theories on infinite series, while Dedekind founds his on the idea of
a cut (Schnitt) in the system
of real numbers, separating all
rational numbers into two
groups having certain characteristic properties. The subject has received later
contributions at the hands of Weierstrass, Leopold Kronecker (Crelle, 101), and Charles Méray.
Continued fractions, closely related to irrational
numbers (and due to Cataldi, 1613), received attention at the hands of Euler,
and at the opening of the 19th century were brought into prominence through the
writings of Joseph Louis Lagrange. Dirichlet also added to the
general theory, as have numerous contributors to the applications of the
subject.
Johann Heinrich Lambert
proved (1761) that π cannot be rational, and that en is
irrational if n is rational (unless n = 0).[27] While
Lambert's proof is often called incomplete, modern assessments support it as
satisfactory, and in fact for its time it is unusually rigorous. Adrien-Marie Legendre (1794), after introducing the
Bessel–Clifford function,
provided a proof to show that π2 is irrational, whence it follows
immediately that π is irrational also. The existence of transcendental numbers was first established by
Liouville (1844, 1851). Later, Georg Cantor (1873) proved their existence by a different method, that
showed that every interval in the reals contains transcendental numbers. Charles Hermite (1873) first
proved e transcendental, and Ferdinand von Lindemann
(1882), starting from Hermite's conclusions, showed the same for π. Lindemann's
proof was much simplified by Weierstrass (1885), still further by David Hilbert (1893), and
was finally made elementary by Adolf Hurwitz and Paul Gordan.
Example proofs[edit]
This section does not cite any references or sources. (June 2013) |
Square roots[edit]
The square root of 2 was the
first number proved irrational, and that article contains a number of proofs.
The golden ratio is another
famous quadratic irrational and there is a simple proof of its irrationality in
its article. The square roots of all natural numbers which are not perfect squares are irrational and a proof may be
found in quadratic irrationals.
General roots[edit]
The proof above for the
square root of two can be generalized using the fundamental theorem of
arithmetic. This asserts that every integer has a unique factorization into primes. Using it we can
show that if a rational number is not an integer then no integral power of it
can be an integer, as in lowest terms there must be a prime in the denominator
that does not divide into the numerator whatever power each is raised to.
Therefore if an integer is not an exact kth power of another
integer then its kth root is irrational.
Logarithms[edit]
Perhaps the numbers most
easy to prove irrational are certain logarithms. Here is a proof by contradiction (reductio ad absurdum) that log2 3 is
irrational. Notice that log2 3 ≈ 1.58 > 0.
Assume log2 3 is rational. For some positive integers m and n, we have
It follows that
India[edit]Geometrical and mathematical problems involving irrational numbers such as
square roots were addressed very early during the Vedic period in India and
there are references to such calculations in the Samhitas,
Brahmanas and more notably in the Sulbha sutras (800 BC or
earlier). (See Bag, Indian Journal of History of Science, 25(1-4), 1990).
It is suggested that Aryabhata (5th century AD) in calculating a value of pi
to 5 significant figures, he used the word āsanna (approaching), to mean that
not only is this an approximation but that the value is incommensurable (or
irrational).
Later, in their treatises, Indian mathematicians wrote on the arithmetic of
surds including addition, subtraction, multiplication, rationalization, as well
as separation and extraction of square roots. (See Datta, Singh, Indian Journal
of History of Science, 28(3), 1993).
Mathematicians like Brahmagupta (in 628 AD) and Bhaskara I (in 629 AD) made
contributions in this area as did other mathematicians who followed. In the 12th
century Bhaskara II evaluated some of these formulas and critiqued them,
identifying their limitations.
During the 14th to 16th
centuries, Madhava of Sangamagrama and
the Kerala school of astronomy and
mathematics discovered the infinite series for several
irrational numbers such as π and certain irrational values of trigonometric functions. Jyesthadeva provided proofs for these infinite
series in the Yuktibhāṣā.[17]
Middle Ages[edit]
In the Middle ages, the development of algebra by Muslim mathematicians
allowed irrational numbers to be treated as algebraic objects.[18] Middle Eastern
mathematicians also merged the concepts of "number" and "magnitude" into a more
general idea of real numbers, criticized Euclid's idea of ratios, developed the theory of composite ratios,
and extended the concept of number to ratios of continuous magnitude.[19] In his
commentary on Book 10 of the Elements, the Persian mathematician Al-Mahani (d. 874/884) examined and classified quadratic irrationals and cubic irrationals. He
provided definitions for rational and irrational magnitudes, which he treated as
irrational numbers. He dealt with them freely but explains them in geometric
terms as follows:[20]
"It will be a rational (magnitude) when we, for instance, say 10, 12, 3%, 6%,
etc., because its value is pronounced and expressed quantitatively. What is not
rational is irrational and it is impossible to pronounce and represent its value
quantitatively. For example: the roots of numbers such as 10, 15, 20 which are
not squares, the sides of numbers which are not cubes
etc."
In contrast to Euclid's
concept of magnitudes as lines, Al-Mahani considered integers and fractions as
rational magnitudes, and square roots and cube roots as irrational magnitudes. He also
introduced an arithmetical approach to the
concept of irrationality, as he attributes the following to irrational
magnitudes:[20]
"their sums or differences, or results of their addition to a rational
magnitude, or results of subtracting a magnitude of this kind from an irrational
one, or of a rational magnitude from it."
The Egyptian mathematician Abū Kāmil Shujā ibn Aslam
(c. 850 – 930) was the first to accept irrational numbers as solutions to quadratic equations or as coefficients in an equation, often in the form of square roots, cube
roots and fourth roots.[21] In the 10th
century, the Iraqi mathematician
Al-Hashimi provided general proofs (rather than geometric demonstrations) for
irrational numbers, as he considered multiplication, division, and other
arithmetical functions.[22] Abū Ja'far al-Khāzin
(900–971) provides a definition of rational and irrational magnitudes, stating
that if a definite quantity is:[23]
"contained in a certain given magnitude once or many times, then this (given)
magnitude corresponds to a rational number. . . . Each time when this (latter)
magnitude comprises a half, or a third, or a quarter of the given magnitude (of
the unit), or, compared with (the unit), comprises three, five, or three fifths,
it is a rational magnitude. And, in general, each magnitude that corresponds to
this magnitude (i.e. to the unit), as one number to another, is rational.
If, however, a magnitude cannot be represented as a multiple, a part
(l/n), or parts (m/n) of a given magnitude, it is
irrational, i.e. it cannot be expressed other than by means of
roots."
Many of these concepts
were eventually accepted by European mathematicians sometime after the Latin translations of the 12th
century. Al-Hassār, a Moroccan mathematician from Fez specializing in Islamic inheritance
jurisprudence during the 12th century, first mentions the use of
a fractional bar, where numerators and denominators are separated by a
horizontal bar. In his discussion he writes, "..., for example, if you are told
to write three-fifths and a third of a fifth, write thus,
."
[24] This same
fractional notation appears soon after in the work of Leonardo Fibonacci in the 13th century.[25]
Modern period[edit]
The 17th century saw imaginary numbers become a
powerful tool in the hands of Abraham de Moivre, and especially of Leonhard Euler. The
completion of the theory of complex numbers in the 19th century entailed the
differentiation of irrationals into algebraic and transcendental numbers, the
proof of the existence of transcendental numbers, and the resurgence of the
scientific study of the theory of irrationals, largely ignored since Euclid. The year 1872 saw the publication of the
theories of Karl Weierstrass (by his pupil Ernst Kossak), Eduard Heine (Crelle's Journal, 74), Georg Cantor (Annalen, 5), and Richard Dedekind. Méray had
taken in 1869 the same point of departure as Heine, but the theory is generally
referred to the year 1872. Weierstrass's method has been completely set forth by
Salvatore Pincherle in 1880,[26] and Dedekind's
has received additional prominence through the author's later work (1888) and
the endorsement by Paul Tannery (1894). Weierstrass, Cantor, and Heine
base their theories on infinite series, while Dedekind founds his on the idea of
a cut (Schnitt) in the system
of real numbers, separating all
rational numbers into two
groups having certain characteristic properties. The subject has received later
contributions at the hands of Weierstrass, Leopold Kronecker (Crelle, 101), and Charles Méray.
Continued fractions, closely related to irrational
numbers (and due to Cataldi, 1613), received attention at the hands of Euler,
and at the opening of the 19th century were brought into prominence through the
writings of Joseph Louis Lagrange. Dirichlet also added to the
general theory, as have numerous contributors to the applications of the
subject.
Johann Heinrich Lambert
proved (1761) that π cannot be rational, and that en is
irrational if n is rational (unless n = 0).[27] While
Lambert's proof is often called incomplete, modern assessments support it as
satisfactory, and in fact for its time it is unusually rigorous. Adrien-Marie Legendre (1794), after introducing the
Bessel–Clifford function,
provided a proof to show that π2 is irrational, whence it follows
immediately that π is irrational also. The existence of transcendental numbers was first established by
Liouville (1844, 1851). Later, Georg Cantor (1873) proved their existence by a different method, that
showed that every interval in the reals contains transcendental numbers. Charles Hermite (1873) first
proved e transcendental, and Ferdinand von Lindemann
(1882), starting from Hermite's conclusions, showed the same for π. Lindemann's
proof was much simplified by Weierstrass (1885), still further by David Hilbert (1893), and
was finally made elementary by Adolf Hurwitz and Paul Gordan.
Example proofs[edit]
This
section does not cite any references or sources.
(June
2013)
This section does not cite any references or sources. (June 2013) |
댓글 없음:
댓글 쓰기