f(f(f(0)))=f(1).
|
(2) |
Comparing equations (1) and (2) we deduce that
f(1)=f(0)+1 ;
that is,
f(1)>f(0) , whence
f cannot be decreasing, let alone
strictly decreasing.
An alternative argument was given by a few correspondents who know some basic
analysis: Because the function that takes
x to
x+1 , namely
f(f(x)) , is bijective, it follows that
f(x) must also be bijective. From a
course in real analysis we know that a decreasing bijection that maps
R onto
R must have a fixed point (namely the
value of
x where its graph intersects the line
y=x ), which would also be a fixed
point of
f(f(x))=x+1 . But this map does not have a
fixed point (since
x=x+1 has no real solution), a
contradiction.
b.
Yes, there exists a strictly decreasing function
g for which
g(g(x))=2x+1 for all
x∈R . Such a function is
Note that
g(x) is decreasing because it is the
equation of a line with negative slope; moreover,
g(g(x))=−2√(−2√x−1−2√)−(1+2√)=2x+1,
as desired.
In fact, we easily see that this is the
only linear function that does the job: a decreasing linear function must
satisfy
g(x)=ax+b for real numbers
a and
b with
a<0 .
g(g(x))=g(ax+b)=a(ax+b)+b=a2x+(ab+b).
Further comments. The reader should explore for himself why
the preceding calculation fails for
f(x)=ax+b when
f(f(x))=x+1 . As for possible uniqueness in
part (b), both Desprez and Humbert observed that (b) has infinitely many
solutions. For all real numbers
a≠12 ,
g(x)={−2a(x+1)−1−21−a(x+1)−1 if x≤−1 if x≥−1
serves as a nonlinear example. Desprez went further and proved that if
a≤0 , or if
a=1 and
b≠0 , then there are no strictly
decreasing functions that satisfy
f(f(x))=ax+b for all
x ; otherwise there are infinitely
many such functions. He showed, furthermore, how to construct all of them: take
an arbitrary continuous strictly decreasing function on an appropriate interval,
then use the functional equation
f(ax+b)=af(x)+b to extend that function to the real
line.
math central
댓글 없음:
댓글 쓰기